ÒThe
knowledge that we value the most is the knowledge for which we can provide the
strongest justifications.Ó
To what
extent would you agree with this claim?
Socrates defined knowledge as Òjustified true beliefÓ. How
we tend to ÔvalueÕ knowledge would most likely depend on the importance we
place on it; hence, it could be said that ÔvalueÕ in this context is
subjective. Additionally, we should also consider the fact that there are
different types of knowledge, and different ways of knowing (i.e. perception,
emotion, reason and language). Consequently, there may also be different
denotations of ÔjustificationÕ. This could be anything from visual evidence,
expressions of thought, or personal validations (e.g. beliefs, values, cultural
convictions, intuition).
In order to determine the strength of a ÔjustificationÕ, we
must examine the various impacts that external factors have on it. Factors such
as cultural or religious beliefs, upbringing, education and even the age we
live in, can affect our perception of what is ÔtrueÕ and ÔacceptableÕ. For
example, if we consider the rapid progress technology has made over the past 50
years or so, we can also observe the changing attitudes that have accompanied
it. Nowadays, when we need to verify information, we only have to type it into
ÒGoogleÓ, or any other web-based search engine, to unearth millions of websites
offering answers. Compare this to only a few decades ago, when people only had
the choice of consulting other people, or books, and travelled to libraries to
do their research. While many may argue that the convenience, and indeed, speed
of the Internet is unmatched, a certain degree of unreliability still exists
when consulting these sources, as information can be posted by anyone from
anywhere.
As a result, the ÔvalueÕ of this knowledge is questionable.
We are also provided with an extraordinary plethora of sources and answers on
the Internet: all possible forms of ÔjustificationÕ. The more information we
are given, the less valuable it becomes to us. Thus, the knowledge claim that
valued knowledge requires strong justification may not apply in this case. From
a personal viewpoint, being confronted by this immense collection of
resources often confuses me
further, rather than enhancing my understanding, as I am never certain which
one will provide me with the most valid answer.
Are some people more likely to value the teachings of elders
in place of modern education? Many ancient cultures are dying out due to
younger generations abandoning their traditional way of life and religious
teachings as they are influenced by and attracted to the urbanised lifestyles
in developing cities. They may disregard rituals that were previously carried
out to Ôplease the GodsÕ as there has been no proof that these ÔGodsÕ exist.
However, we must question whether this change of belief is truly because they
are convinced by the evidence provided by modern science, or because their
personal priorities lie in conforming to modern society, and becoming
independent from the indigenous community.
Humans have a tendency to prefer knowledge that can be
justified easily. As an article from the New York Times states: ÒPeople in this
modern day and age are torn between remaining loyal to their traditional,
religious or cultural beliefs, and conforming to the rest of society in itÕs
Ôage of informationÕ, and adopting rational, logical, possibly agnostic/passive
views on these.Ó For the most part, studying in greater depth what we already
know, is seen by some as being far more useful than spending time uncovering
truths about knowledge we cannot provide empirical proof for. An example of
this is the importance many people place on scientific knowledge. It is agreed
that many theories of modern science are built upon ÔfactsÕ and ÔlawsÕ created
by scientists and thinkers in the past. Experimentation Ð for example, the
Ôsmoke cellÕ experiment to show Brownian motion and thus justify the particle
theory Ð over centuries has provided us with proof for these, proof that has
been observed and justified by more than one individual, thus turning theories
into universal ÔfactsÕ.
Keeping in mind Edward TellerÕs words: ÒA fact is a simple
statement that everyone believes. It is innocent, unless found
guilty. A hypothesis is a novel suggestion that no one wants to
believe. It is guilty, until found effectiveÓ, our faith in science is
questionable. While we rejoice in new discoveries and breakthroughs in
research, we silently disregard the fact that no matter how ground-breaking the
proposal, it remains a ÔtheoryÕ till ÔprovenÕ through empirical knowledge. For
example, quantum physics relies on Ôstring theoryÕ. Atheists or non-believers
in God and other metaphysical beings may sneer at those who adamantly follow
their religious faith, however, they should remember that celebrated scientific
theories without solid ÔproofÕ are as unreliable as the beliefs that God
exists.
For centuries, religious beliefs have presided over science;
with over 80% of the worldÕs population following some form of organised
religious faith, many continue to accept the laws of scriptures in place of
scientific thought today. If the idea that justification was all people needed
to value knowledge was true, would we not discard our religious beliefs once
science triumphed, since ÔobjectiveÕ proof of metaphysical beings and gods has
yet to be found? I, personally, have several Christian friends who study IB
Biology at Higher Level, yet refuse to accept the possibility of Evolution and
strongly maintain the belief that we are all Ôdescendents of Adam and EveÕ.
Thus, we are faced with the question of whether ÔjustificationÕ in this sense
means proof or faith. Ultimately, people believe in what they find easiest to
argue or explain, with solid evidence to reinforce their defence. While relying
on gut feelings and instincts are subjective responses, providing
justifications accepted or used by many is seen as more reliable: we need
objective arguments.
Maths is a subject that is built on logical deduction and
fact, hence, justification of mathematical theories by proof is necessary, and
is of much greater value to us than complex theorems which cannot be proved and
put to use. We cannot intuitively ÔknowÕ when something is right or wrong with
a mathematical equation, instead, we must employ logic, reason and rational
thinking in order to prove its validity. In this case, the knowledge claim that
justified knowledge is more valuable proves to be correct.
In contrast, Art is perceived as an area of knowledge that
is concerned with a predominantly subjective approach: the artist could draw
inspiration from all areas of knowledge and ways of knowing. Thus, subjectivity
is only limited in the sense that it produces approaches/responses from one
individual only; hence procuring several unique responses, rather than one
objective one. Thus, in this case, knowledge does not require strong
justifications to be of value. The artist in question is not interested in
ÔsolvingÕ anything, nor does he wish to ÔproveÕ anything. He has devoted time
and effort into making something meaningful, and his only wish may be to fulfil
his interest in seeing how others react to his creation, or simply to derive
personal satisfaction from it.
When considering Areas of Knowledge like the Arts, the
knowledge we gain and our justifications for it are open to interpretation. We
can only justify our subjective knowledge: the responses evoked within us by
the art itself. Are these internal reactions strong enough to be of value to
us, or do they fail to render themselves as Ôtrue justificationsÕ? Thus, there
is a degree of uncertainty when judging the value of justifications within
areas of knowledge: some subjects seem to demand a personal bias in order to
derive meaning from it; others rely on reason and objective logic to obtain the
ÔtrueÕ answer. The value we place in either of these is purely subjective:
while I feel that knowledge is gained through our subjective responses and
experiences, my friend does not appreciate this viewpoint, and prefers to make
logical deductions as a way of gaining knowledge.
However, there may be times when we are required to put our
biases aside: the study of History involves the examination of primary and
secondary sources, information that provides ÔevidenceÕ for events that took
place in the past. Yet, possessing a large number of sources to back up claims
is not enough; these sources need to be tested for reliability, and biases must
be noted. Thus, these sources are limited in their justification of the events:
here, the value of knowledge does depend on the strength of the justification.
Conversely, we could consider a counterclaim: the study of Ethics often asks us
to question the reasoning behind so-called Ômoral truthsÕ. For example, we know
that murder is ÔwrongÕ. But why is it wrong? People prefer to accept views like
this without proper justification, because there is a certain challenge
involved in attempting to explain this standpoint logically.
While it may be conventionally accepted that knowledge
accompanied by convincing justifications is preferred to knowledge based merely
on speculation, I disagree with the claim that only fully justified knowledge
is valued. If ÔvalueÕ is to be interpreted in terms of importance to an
individual, then it is impossible to generalise and pass off an objective
statement. For example, many people may disregard intuition as a way of
knowing, however, it still plays a very important role in our lives: an
inexplicable feeling of discomfort or nervousness would still affect us. As
previously discussed, it is possible that the knowledge we may treasure the
most is that which has not yet been broken down, analysed and deprived of
further exploration. Hence, it may be the unjustifiable knowledge, the unknown
truths about religion, life after death, the universe and human nature that we
value. The value of knowledge is based on its importance to us, and is ultimately,
a subjective decision.
BIBLIOGRAPHY:
First Science, http://www.firstscience.com/home/poems-and-quotes/quotes/edward-teller-quote_2312.html
(Accessed on Dec 20th 2008)
Plato, Theaetetus. Translated by Robin Waterfield; published
by Penguin Classics, 1987.
Steinfels, Peter. ÒDo You Believe in God? A. Yes, No
and Well. . .Ó New
York Times
http://www.nytimes.com/2007/11/10/us/10beliefs.html,
Published: November 10, 2007. on November
29th 2008)
World Religious Statistics Summary, http://www.geocities.com/richleebruce/mystat.html
(Accessed on Dec 20th 2008)