The Problem with Facts
There are at least six
constituents which need to be considered when deciding what is a fact, or
better still what will be considered by us as facts:
1.
The limitations of the
human organism: the human sensory apparatus determines the range of
facts. Note also the relevance of the human life span. Would a race of
intelligent animals that live for only an hour be
likely ever to discover that glaciers drift? or that a
melody is being played on a phonograph record revolving once a century?
2.
The scientific instruments available. “Fact” is
relative to the methods and conditions of observation - to the accuracy of
thermometers, yardsticks, and clocks: things do not have a “size” which is
independent of the instruments used to measure it. (And of course instruments
cannot dispense with the human observer; even a computer print-out must be read
at some point by a person.)
3.
Memory. One can be aware of repetition or of generality only if one
now has a sense of what has occurred in the past.
4.
The personality, aims, and bias of the individual
scientist. This factor is usually (perhaps not always?) corrected for by other
scientists.
5.
Language. The observer can describe the world only in the language
available to him. Wittgenstein said that “if we spoke a different language, we
would perceive a somewhat different world.” Waismann’s
metaphor is “language is the knife with which we cut out facts.” There is no
“fact of the matter” outside language.
6.
Most significantly, fact is relative to hypothesis. There
are no “raw facts.” The human eye is not a camera, unfocused, automatically and
unselectively recording impressions. Facts are not found haphazardly, nor in isolation. The scientist is not a passive observer of
a self-evident structure. The scientist must know what to look for. He must
select; he must evaluate; he works from an implicit theory which determines
what he will consider as a relevant fact. To ask for “nothing but the facts!”
is to demand a map drawn to no particular scale.
Interestingly, then it
seems as if it is the hypothesis that is important in determining what facts we
will find out, which seems to be the wrong way round as we usually think of the
facts as determining whether or not the hypothesis is true, not the reverse …
and this leads us to some interesting problems. What if a scientist has the
wrong theory / hypothesis? Will she miss an important piece of evidence that is
vital to her understanding of the world? Malinowski tells of a young
anthropologist who went out in the field to record a certain tribal ritual. He
dutifully photographed everything in sight, only to realize later that the
significant part of the ceremony was taking place somewhere else but he didn’t
know where to look because he had the wrong theory about what was important
According to Whitehead,
science tries “to see what is general in what is particular.” But the problem
is that the particular thing always has more than one general aspect or
property that you could be talking about. Gomperz
offers the following descriptions of the flight of a sparrow:
There goes a sparrow.
This bird is flying.
Here is an animal.
Something here is moving.
Energy here is being
transformed.
This is not a case of
perpetual motion.
The poor thing is
frightened.
No description can tell
you all that can be told about a particular thing or event; “fact is richer
than diction” and so a scientist will have to decide what are the relevant
factors to talk about / look at / investigate and that will probably be decided
by the particular theory they have which will tell them what is important. So,
in the above example the physicist’s theory might tell him that the important
thing to look at when investigating why the bird flies is the transformation of
energy with the psychological aspect of fear being relatively irrelevant. This
makes sense, after all you can’t investigate
everything, but what if the scientists have the wrong theory?
As a TOK student it is
important to realize that Science is not always the purely objective quest
after facts that it is sometimes made out to be. This has had some interesting
effects on the way that science has been pursued, particularly when we look at
how scientists’ views about what facts need to be explained have changed and
developed over time. There are always implicit assumptions about what facts are
puzzling and what might be taken for granted and here are a few examples:
1.
The Ancient Greeks did not think that how the world began
had to be explained.
2.
Francis Bacon refused to believe Copernicus theory that the
sun is at the center of the solar system because it seemed nonsense to him to
group the earth, which is motionless and dark, with the other planets which
move and shine.
3.
Kepler was puzzled as to why
each planet is at a particular distance from the Sun but now we are just happy
to accept that the particular distance of the Earth and all of the other
planets is just an accident, in our case a lucky one.
4.
X Rays were discovered in 1900 when Roentgen wondered why a
screen glowed unaccountably but before him no one else had thought that this
glowing needed an explanation.
5.
No one before Descartes thought that the relationship
between Mind and Body was a problem.
6.
In current Physics there is no need to explain why the speed
of light is constant, it just is!
7.
Equally in Nuclear Physics it is believed that there is no
need to explain why radioactive decay happens when it does, it just happens.
8.
Does the fact that space has three dimensions have to be
explained?
As you can see what a
scientist feel does or does not need to be explained is strongly influenced by
their theory and their position in the history of scientific thought but let us
not lose too much heart. let us also
remember The judgment of scientists may be biased, their selection of problems may
be whimsical, their assessment of the evidence may be faulty, their
determination of the facts may be subjective, their motivations may be suspect,
and their observations may be distorted by their values: beware the fisherman
who uses a net with two-inch openings and declares that all the fish in the
ocean are larger than two inches! But these factors may all be made explicit,
and controlled. Science is a social and self-corrective enterprise.
The human element in the
progress of scientific explanation cannot be eliminated. The usual image of the
scientist is misleading. He is not finding his way through a labyrinth which
has one and only one pathway through it (there may be more than one, and there
may be none). He is not putting together the pieces of a jigsaw puzzle (that
is, pieces which can be correctly joined in one way only). He is not solving a
mathematical problem, nor a chess puzzle: both
mathematics and chess presuppose specific postulates and rules of inference.
Nature proffers no rules, no definitions, no stipulations, no guides, no Ariadne’s thread. We make all
these up ourselves. It is not nature which prevents our grouping cabbages with
kings, but our own demands for order. And we have no reason to believe that our
categories and discoveries and conclusions are the only ones possible.
Our perceptual knowledge
is delimited by our characteristic biological capacities, and there are limits
to the completeness of our theoretical structures. But our observations and our
theories mutually reinforce each other. If we never trusted some sort of
evidence, nothing whatever could ever be tested. The structure of our science
is pragmatically justified; it is the most reliable knowledge there is; it is
in every sense objective.
But it is our science;
it alleviates our puzzlement; it supplies the answers to the questions we
have asked. Nature answers - if she answers at all! - only
those questions which we put to her. Man is nature becoming aware of herself, but she might have other children! If there should
exist intelligent creatures elsewhere in the universe, will their “science”
inevitably be the same as ours? At the court of Louis XIV there was an ongoing
debate as to whether two “perfect artists” painting the same scene would
produce identical pictures. Would two “perfect scientists” working
independently produce identical sciences? Both of these questions imply that
regardless of how the problem is viewed, regardless of the human mind, there is
only one correct solution. But there is no reason to believe that any such
unique solution exists. There is an irreducibly anthropocentric element in
knowledge. No observation, no measurement, no thought process ever confirms a
hypothesis with absolute precision. We can never be certain in an experiment
that we have excluded all extraneous factors, nor what degree of error may be
tolerated, nor what other explanations may be possible. Answers to questions
have contexts, and presuppositions. We can no more explain everything at once
than we can doubt everything at once. The decision as to when to accept an
explanation and when to question it is ultimately and idiosyncratically human.
We are thus again
referred back to the primal philosophic injunction: Know thyself (Socrates)!
Man is the measure.
Adapted from Reuben Abel’s ‘Man is the Measure’ (Chapter 10)