Crime
and Custom in Savage Society ¡V Bronislav Malinowski
In these extracts from
Crime and Custom in Savage Society (first published in 1926 in
It is also interesting to
see how even such an open-minded and experienced thinker still refers to people
from less developed countries as savages and natives and how he also refers,
without any moral qualms, to the way in which Western powers might use the
knowledge provided by anthropologists to more successfully exploit ¡¥the
native¡¦.
Similarly, we can see the
views of other anthropologists reflected in Malinowski¡¦s work and it appears
that many of them seem to equate savagery with a kind of Communism. Although I
have no hard evidence for this it certainly seems plausible to argue that
Western thinkers, frightened by the threat of Communism in East, might
associate it with a descent into savagery and so look for indications of
communism among savage tribes.
In this way not only do
the extracts below help to shed light on the similarities between indigenous
knowledge systems and other knowledge systems ¡K but they also reveal how an
area of knowledge can change and develop over time, how it can grow or diminish
in credibility and how its concerns and focus can shift and evolve.
1.
¡¥Savagery is still
synonymous with absurd, cruel and eccentric customs, with quaint superstitions
and revolting practices. Sexual license, infanticide, head-hunting, couvade, cannibalism and what not, have made anthropology
attractive reading to many, a subject of curiosity rather than of serious
scholarship to others ¡K [However,] a fuller knowledge of the
so-called savages has revealed ¡¥ye heathen¡¦ [to be, just as we are,] a product
of firm law and of strict tradition, due to the biological, mental and social
needs to of human nature rather than as the outcome of unbridled passion and
unfettered excess. [As in the civilized world,] law and order pervade the
tribal usages of primitive races, they govern all the hum drum course of daily
existence, as well as the leading acts of public life.¡¦ (pp. 1-2)
2.
¡¥Anthropology is still to
most laymen and to many specialists mainly an object of antiquarian interest ¡K
There are, however, certain aspects of anthropology which are of a genuine
scientific character in that they do not lead us beyond empirical fact into the
realms of uncontrollable conjecture, in that they widen our knowledge of human
nature, and are capable of direct practical application. I mean such a subject,
for example, as primitive economics, important for our knowledge of man¡¦s
economic disposition and of value to those who wish to develop the resources of
tropical countries, employ indigenous labour and
trade with the natives. Or again, a subject such as the comparative study of he
mental processes of savages, a line of research which has already proved
fertile to psychology and might be made useful to those engaged in educating or
morally improving the native. Last, but not least, there is the subject of
primitive law, the study of the various forces that make for order, uniformity
and cohesion in a savage tribe. The
knowledge of these forces should have formed the foundation of anthropological
theories of primitive organization and should have yielded the guiding
principles of Colonial legislation and administration.¡¦ (pp. 1-2)
3. ¡¥The early German students of savage law were all and one
committed to the hypothesis of ¡¥primitive promiscuity¡¦ and ¡¥group marriage¡¦ ¡K
[and this myth of group marriage cast such a shadow on all their arguments that
their theories were infected by the concepts of] ¡¥group-responsibility¡¦,
¡¥group-justice¡¦, ¡¥group property¡¦ and ¡¥communism¡¦ in short, with the dogma of
the absence of individual rights and liabilities among savages.
Underlying all those
ideas was the assumption that in primitive societies the individual is
completely dominated by the group ¡V the horde, the clan or the tribe ¡V that he
obeys the commands of his community its traditions, its public opinion, its
decrees, with a slavish, fascinated, passive obedience. This assumption, which
gives the leading tone to certain modern discussions upon the mentality and sociality
of savages still survives [in some places].
Thus handicapped by
insufficient material and baseless assumptions, the early school of
anthropological jurisprudence was driven into an impasse of artificial and
sterile constructions. In
consequence, it proved to incapable of real vitality,
and the whole interest in the subject heavily slumped.¡¦ (pp. 3-4)
4. ¡¥When we come to inquire why rules of conduct, however hard,
irksome, or unwelcome are obeyed; what ,makes private life, economic
cooperation, public events run so smoothly; of what, in short, consist the
forces of law and order in savagery ¡V the answer is not easy to give, and what
anthropology had to say about it is far from satisfactory. So long as it could
be maintained that the ¡¥savage¡¦ is really savage, that he follows what little
law he has but fitfully and loosely, the problem did not exist. When the
question became actually, when it became plain that hypertrophy of rules rather
than lawlessness is characteristic of primitive life, scientific opinion veered
round to the opposite point: the savage was made not only into a model of the
law-abiding citizen, but it became an axiom that in submitting to all his
tribal rules and fetters, he follows the natural trend of his spontaneous
impulses; that in this way he glides, so to speak, along the line of least
resistance.
The savage, so runs today¡¦s verdict
of competent anthropologists, has a deep reverence for tradition and custom, an
automatic submission to their biddings. He obeys them ¡¥slavishly¡¦, ¡¥unwittingly¡¦,
¡¥spontaneously¡¦, through ¡¥mental inertia¡¦, combined with the fear of public
opinion or of supernatural punishment; or again through a ¡¥pervading group
sentiment if not group instinct¡¦. Thus we find the following in a recent book:
¡¥The savage is far from being the free and unfettered creature of Rousseau¡¦s
imagination. On the contrary, he is hemmed in on every side by the customs of
his people, he is bound in he chains of immemorial tradition not merely in his
social relations but in his religion, his medicine, in his industry and his
art: in short every aspect of his life¡¦ (E. Sidney Hartland in Primitive Law p.
138). With all this we might agree, but when we are told that ¡¥these fetters
are accepted by him as a matter of course; he never seeks to break forth¡¦ we
must enter a protest. Is it not contrary to human nature to accept any
constraint as a matter of course, and does man, whether civilized or savage,
ever carry out unpleasant, burdensome, cruel regulations and taboos without
being compelled to? And compelled by some force or motive which he cannot
resist?
Yet this automatic acquiescence,
this instinctive submission of every member of the tribe to its laws, is the
fundamental axiom laid at the basis of the inquiry into primitive order and
adherence to rule. Thus another foremost authority on the subject, the late Dr.
Rivers, speaks in the book already mentioned of an ¡¥unwitting or intuitive method
of regulating social life¡¦ which is, according to him ¡¥closely connected with
primitive communism¡¦ And he proceeds to tell us: ¡¥Among such people as the
Melanesians there is a group sentiment which makes unnecessary any definite
social machinery for the exertion of authority, in just the same manner as it
makes possible the harmonious working of communal ownership, and insures the
peaceful character of a communistic system of sexual relations¡¦ (Social
Organisation p.169)
Thus here again we are assured that
¡¥unwitting¡¦ or ¡¥intuitive methods¡¦, ¡¥instinctive submission¡¦ and some
mysterious ¡¥group sentiment¡¦ account for law, order, communism, and sexual
promiscuity alike! This sounds altogether like a Bolshevik paradise, but is
certainly not correct in reference to the Melanesian societies which I know at
first hand.
¡K It would be easy to multiply
statements and to show that the dogma of the automatic submission to custom
dominates the whole inquiry into primitive law. ¡K The extreme difficulty of the
problem lies, I think, in the very diffuse and complex nature of the forces
which constitute primitive law. Accustomed as we are to look for a definite machinery for the enforcement of law (e.g. a
police force or court system) we cast round for something analogous in a savage
community and, failing to find there any similar arrangements, conclude that
all law is obeyed by this mysterious propensity of the savages to obey it. By
defining the forces of law in terms of central authority, codes, courts and
constables, we must come to the conclusion that law needs no enforcement in a
primitive community and that it is followed spontaneously.
[However, based on my observations,
it has become clear to me that even when the savage does follow the law his behavior,
like ours,] is at best partial, conditional, and subject to evasions; that it
is not enforced by any wholesale motive like fear of punishment or a general
submission to all tradition but [again like us] by a very complex network of
psychological and social inducements.
All of this is a state of affairs
which modern anthropology has overlooked but in the following account I shall
try to establish it for one ethnographic province: North-West Melanesia, and I
shall show reasons why observations of similar nature to those carried out by
myself should be extended to all other societies in order to give us some idea
about their legal conditions.¡¦ (pp. 9-15)
5. ¡¥If we designate the sum total of rules, conventions and
patterns of behavior as the body of custom, there is no doubt that the native
feels a strong respect for all of them, has a tendency to do what others do,
what everyone approves of, and, if not drawn or drive in another direction by
his appetites or interests, will follow the bidding of custom rather than any
other force The force of habit, the awe of traditional command and a
sentimental attachment to it, the desire to satisfy public opinion ¡V all
combine to make custom be obeyed for its own sake. In this the ¡¥savages¡¦ do not
differ from the members of any self-contained community with a limited horizon,
whether tis be an Eastern European ghetto, an
[For example,] there are among the Trobrianders [the island race studied by Malinowski] a
number of traditional rules instructing the craftsman how to ply his trade. The
inert and uncritical way in which these rules are obeyed [is less to do with
conformism than] because their practical utility is recognized by reason and
testified by experience. Again, other injunctions of how to behave in
associating with your friends, superiors, equals and so on, are obeyed because
any deviation from them makes a man feel and look, in the eyes of others,
ridiculous, clumsy or socially uncouth. [In this way it can be seen that the savage
follows rules for very similar reasons to the civilized man].¡¦ (pp. 51 ¡V 52)
6. ¡¥The rules of law stand out from the rest in that they are
felt and regarded as the obligations of one person and the rightful claims of
another. They are sanctioned not by a mere psychological motive, but by a
definite social machinery of binding force, based, [as in the West], upon
mutual dependence and realized in the equivalent arrangement of reciprocal
services. The ceremonial manner in which most transactions are carried out,
which entails public control and criticism, adds still more to their binding
force.
We may therefore finally dismiss the
view that ¡¥group sentiment¡¦ or ¡¥collective responsibility¡¦ is the only or even
the main force which ensures adhesion to custom and which makes it binding and
legal. Esprit de corps, solidarity, pride in one¡¦s community and clan exist
undoubtedly among the Melanesians ¡V no social order could be maintained without
them in any culture high or low ¡V [but it would be ridiculous] to make this
unselfish, impersonal, unlimited group loyalty the corner stone of all social
order in primitive cultures. The savage is neither an extreme
¡¥collectivist¡¦ or an intransigent ¡¥individualist¡¦ ¡V he is, like man in
general, a mixture of both.¡¦ (pp. 55¡V56)
7.
¡¥[As with civilized man,
civil law for the savage] is extremely well developed and is clearly
distinguished by the native from other types of norm, whether morals or
manners, rules of art or commands of religion. The rules of their law, far from
being rigid, absolute or issued in the Divine Name are [like ours] maintained
by social forces, understood as rational and necessary, elastic and capable of
adjustment.¡¦ (p. 74)